Adam Smith, revolutionary

Spencer A. Leonard
Platypus Review 61
.

By exposing the historical necessity that had brought capitalism into being, political economy became the critique of history as a whole.

— Theodor W. Adorno[1]

Unlike Jean-Jacques Rousseau or even Friedrich Nietzsche, Adam Smith is a thinker few on the contemporary Left will have much time for. This tells us more about the impoverishment of the currently prevailing intellectual environment than about the persistent, if ever more obscure, influence of bourgeois radicalism on the Left. Today, of course, it is fashionable to have “a critique of the enlightenment” or, alternatively, to defend it against an array of enemies, including postmodernism, religious conservatism, and academic obscurantism. Those currents of the contemporary Left that still seek to lay claim to the Enlightenment must fend off Smith, because, like Rousseau, his is an Enlightenment that cannot be upheld simply as an affirmation of “reason” or the demand for “human rights.” Smith’s Enlightenment demands to be advanced. His 1776 treatise, An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations, is not a product of the Scottish Enlightenment but of the cosmopolitan radical Enlightenment, stretching from the coffeehouses of Rotterdam to the meeting rooms of Calcutta. If that cosmopolitan Enlightenment project remains “unfinished,” it is because the course of history since the publication of Smith’s magnum opus failed to fulfill and indeed undermined the radical potentials of the eighteenth century.

Cornwallis’ 1781 surrender at Yorktown, where American soldiers sang the British Revolutionary song “The World Turned Upside Down”

Cornwallis’ 1781 surrender at Yorktown, where American soldiers
sang the British Revolutionary song “World Turned Upside Down”

Smith’s powerful influence upon French revolutionaries such as the Abbé Sieyes and the Marquis de Condorcet, and through them upon Immanuel Kant, Benjamin Constant, and G.W.F. Hegel, are not as well known as they should be, but that need not detain us from coming to terms with the profound radicalism of his thought. Less well known still is the respect that Smith and his close friend, David Hume, held for Rousseau’s works. Hume, refusing to allow his famous public quarrel with Rousseau to cloud his judgment, contended in a letter to Smith that the Genevan’s writings were “efforts of genius.”[2] This was an estimate Hume doubtless knew would find favor with his friend, since as early as 1756 Smith had written an article that is perhaps the earliest discussion in English of Rousseau’s Discourse on the Origin and Basis of Inequality Among Men, singling that work out as the act whereby the Francophone world re-established its supremacy in philosophy for the first time since Descartes, displacing the preeminence of English political and social thought that had lasted for almost a century with the writings of Hobbes, Locke, Mandeville, Shaftesbury, and others.[3] Nor did Smith’s devotion to Rousseau, proclaimed in this early publication, abate towards the end of his life. For we have the testimony to the contrary of Faujas de Saint-Fond from 1784:

When I was taking tea with him, [Smith] spoke to me of Rousseau with a kind of religious respect. “Voltaire,” said he, “sought to correct the vices and the follies of mankind by laughing at them, and sometimes even getting angry with them; Rousseau, by the attraction of sentiment, and the force of conviction, drew the reader into the heart of reason. His Contrat Social will in time avenge him for all the persecutions he has suffered.”[4]

Smith’s profound sympathy with Rousseau’s epoch-making philosophy found its highest expression in the radical political economy put forward in the Wealth of Nations, which laid the groundwork for the revolutionary wave of the late eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries no less than did the Discourse on Inequality and the Social Contract. Indeed, Smith, as much as Georges Danton or Maximilien de Robespierre, was a leading bourgeois revolutionary.

In order to fully grasp the radical specification of Rousseau’s call for the conscious advance of human freedom contained in Smith’s work — that is, in order to grasp the work’s bourgeois-revolutionary implications — readers and interpreters must get beyond the outward sobriety of the Wealth of Nations to the “very violent attack…upon the whole commercial system” that lies at its core.[5] Living in the most revolutionary society of his age, Smith was nevertheless not complacent. He, no less than Rousseau, demanded a revolutionary transformation of his society, railing with all his strength of intellect against what Rousseau called “our absurd civil institutions whereby the real welfare of the public and true justice are always sacrificed to some apparent order, which is in reality detrimental to all order and which merely gives the sanction of public authority to the oppression of the weak and the iniquity of the strong.”[6] It was in full recognition of the flagging of British philosophy and, with it, of the British revolution, that Adam Smith wrote a work that was, in its way, not only the most revolutionary of 1776, but also the crucial text, along with the Abbé Raynal’s A Philosophical and Political History of the Settlements and Trade of the Europeans in the East and West Indies, linking Rousseau to the French Revolution and German Idealism.

An 18th-century pin factory, from the Encyclopédie edited by Denis Diderot and Jean le Rond d’Alembert, 1751-1772

An 18th-century pin factory, from the Encyclopédie edited by
Denis Diderot and Jean le Rond d’Alembert, 1751-1772

Smith is one of those indispensable eighteenth-century thinkers who articulates unmistakably that century’s critique of our own interminable twentieth century. Profoundly, even originally, aware of the depth of the self-transformative potential of humanity, Smith demands that we transform ourselves. Author of one of the greatest acts of public reason ever penned, Smith demands that our time too make a thoroughgoing attack upon the entire commercial system. Prophet of cosmopolitan civil society, Smith would be outraged at the mockery made of it by contemporary globalization. Revolutionary diagnostician of the social ground of freedom, he would condemn not only statist capitalism but also no less certainly market capitalism’s integral connection with, and extension of, its own monstrous outgrowth, the Bonapartist state. But rather than recognize and potentially advance this critique, the desiccated thought of what passes for Marxism or, for that matter, of what passes for liberalism, can only adopt a posture of knowing superiority respecting Smith about whose thought it does not have a clue.

Take, for example, the prominent Marx scholar David Harvey, whose writings are part of the gospel of the contemporary academic and activist Left. Harvey describes Smith as a “liberal utopian” committed to a theology of “perfectly functioning markets and the hidden hand.”[7] A spokesman for the capitalist class, Harvey’s Smith promotes their exploitative system as a “utopianism of process” from which he helpfully “derive[s] a political program,” the essence of which Harvey states as follows: “Give free markets room to flourish, then all will be well with the world.” By way of closing, Harvey does not fail to instruct his reader that “this, of course, is the ideology that has become so dominant in certain of the advanced capitalist countries…these last 20 years.” Smith represents a set of policy prescriptions against which, presumably, the Marxist David Harvey has others to oppose. And, surely, we can all agree that “Marx mounted a devastating attack upon this utopianism of process in Capital.”[8]

But Harvey should not be singled out. Rather, he expresses something like the conventional view of the matter — while we might puzzle over Marx’s relationship to, perhaps dialectical appropriation of, Hegel’s dialectic, Marx’s critique of political economy is an attack, a refutation, or at least a criticism. It would be truer to say that Capital is closed to Harvey, despite his being that book’s “leading interpreter” in these spiritless times, precisely because the Wealth of Nations is impenetrable to him. That Smith represents a major stage in the development of the labor theory of value — formulating for the first time, for instance, the distinction between productive and unproductive labor — is of no concern to the likes of Harvey. At the heart of Smith’s project is the attempt to advance, in theory and practice, the radical emancipation entailed in free wage-labor. This social emancipation — that is, the freedom of labor to sell itself on the market unconstrained by the demands of customary privilege — is utterly obscured by Harvey’s anachronistic talk of “free-market” regulatory policy. Nor is the more overwrought Marxology of a Michael Heinrich any stronger on the question of Marx’s relation to Smith and to bourgeois political economy more generally. Understanding Marx to be anti-bourgeois, Heinrich consigns to the dustbin of “worldview Marxism” all those who might imagine that Marx’s thought is in any way immanent to political economy.[9]

3447151228_91f04488c9_o

Statue of Adam Smith, 19th century

As a systematic labor theorist of value, Smith proves himself an indispensable philosopher of the revolutionary Third Estate. For him, the world of commercial society is one grounded in the free labor of a newly emergent class, a class of city-dwellers freed from serfdom and customary claims. The city-dwellers or “bourgeois” of the late medieval and early modern period share in a common freedom, worker and merchant alike. Their society, as Smith outlines in Book Three of the Wealth of Nations, emerges as a result of what can only be dubbed a slave revolt in what had been a relatively obscure corner of Europe. This slave revolt, incidentally, has not ceased to this day, and not just in the sense that it has spread from Western Europe to other parts of the world. The masses of humanity, including in Europe and America, have not ceased to demand a world in which they do not require the benevolence or indulgence of the baker, the butcher, the brewer, or anyone else in order to live their lives as they choose under the law. To this day, this emancipation is only available to the broad masses of the population in precisely the way in which Smith demanded it, i.e. by wage labor. To this day, the great democratic demand is that people should be subject to no arbitrary power of wealth, but only to that power that “possession immediately and directly conveys” [48] to the owner of money: command over labor.

What Smith termed “commercial society” is best understood precisely as the interrelationships of people exchanging the products of labor. As he famously wrote:

When the division of labor has been once thoroughly established it is but a very small part of a man’s wants which the produce of his own labor can supply. He supplies the far greater part of them by exchanging…Every man thus lives by exchanging, or becomes in some measure a merchant, and the society itself grows to be what is properly [called] a commercial society. [37]

That such a commercial society is class divided represents for Smith an achievement, one that simultaneously exposes as irrational the prescriptive claims of all past ruling classes and, indeed, of the ruling classes of his own day. If we still say that the history of all hitherto existing societies is the history of class society, those societies and that history is simultaneously worthy of condemnation for having failed to have been. That is because they failed to recognize and realize themselves as class societies, and were thus inadequate to the concept of society itself. In other words, all wealth is originally labor, from which, after the claims arising from “the accumulation of stock and the appropriation of land” [65] are deducted as profit and rents, those who expect in addition, say, personal deference or sexual favors fail to recognize (and must again be made to understand) that this is a class society. As Adorno remarks, crediting the 19th century legal historian J.C. Bluntschli, “society…[is] a concept of the third estate.”[10]

Though the fact is inimical to most leftists, the historical emergence of freedom was occasioned by the demand for class society. The demand for work, i.e. the demand to be subject only to the social power that properly appertains to money, led to that world-historical liberation from “community” that we call the birth of the modern individual. This demand for freedom from the need to rely upon the benevolence of others, this struggle for free wage-labor, remains the greatest social movement on earth. It should not be thought that workers and those struggling for employment are simply resigned to working for a master. Rather, the worker’s demand for work must be viewed as simultaneously a demand for a form of private property adequate to its concept.

Russian translation of Adam Smith's Wealth of Nations, published by the Communist Party of the USSR (1962)

Russian translation of Adam Smith’s Wealth of Nations,
published by the Communist Party of the USSR (1962)

Driven to dialectics by his struggle against the French Physiocrats and the British mercantilists, Smith overturns all past political economy. Though his work is chiefly associated with the demand for free markets and the “invisible hand,” none of this is in fact peculiar to Smith. Rather, as part and parcel of the project of the revolutionary Third Estate reaching back into the seventeenth century, these were mainstream concerns of political economy from at least the time of John Locke and Sir Dudley North. Similarly, the character and productive potential of the division of labor, so closely associated with Smith’s name, forms a subject of intense reflection and analysis nearly three-quarters of a century before the Wealth of Nations in the writings of Sir William Petty. The neglect of what is novel in Smith goes hand in hand with the one-sided rejection of liberalism and of the bourgeois revolutions.

What is in fact central to Smith’s work is the fundamental clarification of labor as the category at the heart of bourgeois freedom. This further specification of modern freedom reaches toward Ricardo and the Ricardian theorists of the labor movement, as well as the nineteenth century more generally, inasmuch as Smith raises not only the question of the emergence of class society, but also of the Third Estate’s internal capacity for class division. As Smith notes:

We have no acts of parliament against combining to lower the [wages of labor], but many against combining to raise it…We rarely hear, it has been said, of the combinations of masters; though frequently of those of workmen. But whoever imagines, upon this account, that masters rarely combine, is as ignorant of the world as of the subject. Masters are always and everywhere in a sort of tacit, but constant and uniform combination, not to raise the wages of labour…To violate this combination is every where a most unpopular action, and a sort of reproach to a master among his neighbors and equals. We seldom, indeed, hear of this combination, because it is the usual, and one may say, the natural state of things which nobody ever hears of…[The workers’ combinations, by contrast,] are desperate [as they] act with the folly and extravagance of desperate men who must either starve or frighten their masters into an immediate compliance with their demands. The masters upon these occasions are not as clamorous upon the other side, [yet] they never cease to call aloud for the assistance of the civil magistrate and the rigorous execution of [anti-labor laws]. [84-5]

As Smith remarks clinching the matter, “A man must always live by his work” [85]. And, just as Smith reaches toward Ricardo and Ricardian theorists in his analysis of class formation, so he also connects the revolutionary Third Estate to its progeny and heir, the nineteenth-century workers’ movement, by calling not only for the emancipation of labor but also for the fulfillment of that emancipation in the struggle for higher wages and better working conditions. On this matter, the Wealth of Nations could not be clearer:

[A man’s] wages must at least be sufficient to maintain him. They must even upon most occasions be somewhat more; otherwise it would be impossible for him to bring up a family, and the race of workmen would not last beyond the first generation…differences in the mode of subsistence [of workers] is not the cause but the effect of the difference in wages; though by a strange misapprehension, I have frequently heard it represented as the cause. It is not because one man keeps a coach while his neighbor walks afoot that the one is rich and the other poor, but because the one is rich he keeps a coach, and because the other is poor he walks afoot…Is improvement in the circumstance of the lower ranks of the people to be regarded as an advantage or as an inconvenience to society. The answer seems abundantly plain…The liberal reward of labor, as it is the effect of increasing wealth, so it is the cause of increasing population. To complain of it is to lament over the necessary effect and cause of the greatest public prosperity. [85, 93, 96, 99]

Thus, while demanding legal protection for labor’s right to organize, Smith could still hope, and moreover hope in good faith, that bourgeois freedom realized in and through the supremacy of economics would one day lead to the emancipation of laboring humanity.

Profile of Adam Smith, 18th century

Profile of Adam Smith, 18th century

It is the commitment to philosophy and freedom that confers forthrightness upon the great scientific pronouncements of the bourgeois class as exemplified by the author of the Wealth of Nations. Such bourgeois revolutionary thought stands, as might well be expected from a self-proclaimed devotee of Rousseau, as an indictment of “the history of all hitherto existing societies,” including that of Smith’s own day. Marxism and its critique of political economy represent the continuation of this revolutionary bourgeois tradition, albeit in changed conditions. It is by no means the repudiation of Smith’s radical Enlightenment. For Marxism seeks in its struggle to advance social-political emancipation not to redeem history from the wreckage of Smith’s “utopianism of process”; rather, it seeks to redeem Smith’s project from the wreckage of history. Under conditions of capital, Smith’s thought itself demands its own critique.

Notes 


All references to Smith’s Wealth of Nations in what follows are to the two volume edition edited by R..H. Campbell and Andrew Skinner (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1976). References will be provided in the text in brackets.

1. Theodor W. Adorno, “Reflections on Class Theory,” in Can One Live After Auschwitz? A Philosophical Reader, edited by Rolf Tiedemann (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2003, 93.
2. David Hume to Adam Smith 10/17/1767, in Correspondence of Adam Smith, ed. E. C. Mossner and I. S. Ross (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1976), 137.
3. Smith’s early opinion of Rousseau could not have been higher. Thus in the second essay Smith ever published, he writes,

The original and inventive genius of the English has…discovered itself…in morals, metaphysics, and part of the abstract sciences. Whatever attempts have been made in modern times towards improvement in this contentious and unprosperous philosophy have been made in England. The Meditations of Descartes excepted, I know of nothing in French that aims at being original…[However,] English philosophy…seems now to be neglected by the English themselves…[and to have been] transported into France…, above all in the late Discourse on Inequality by Mr. Rousseau of Geneva. [“Letter to the Edinburgh Review” [1756], in W.P.D. Wightman and J.C. Bryce (eds.), Essays on Philosophical Subjects (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1980), 250-51.

4. Barthélemy Faujas de Saint-Fond, A Journey Through England and Scotland to the Hebrides in 1784, vol. 2, edited by Sir Archibald Geikie (Glasgow, H. Hopkins, 1907), 246.
5. Adam Smith to Andreas Holt 10/26/1780, in Correspondence, 251.
6. Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Confessions, trans. J.M. Cohen (London: Penguin Books, 1953), 306.
7. David Harvey, A Companion to Marx’s Capital (New York: Verso, 2010), 52.
8. David Harvey, Spaces of Hope (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2000), 175.
9. For the view that bourgeois political economists such as Smith have fallen prey to “an image of reality that develops independently as a result of the everyday practice of the members of bourgeois society,” see Michael Heinrich, An Introduction to Marx’s Three Volumes of Capital, translated by Alexander Locascio (New York: Monthly Review Press, 2012), 34-5.
10. T.W. Adorno, “Society” translated by F.R. Jameson Salmagundi 10-11 (1969-70), 144. Elsewhere Adorno elaborates saying,

The societalization of society, its consolidation into what…is more truly like a system than an organism, has resulted from the principle of domination, the principle of division itself, and it perpetuates it. Society has survived, reproduced, and extended itself, and has developed its forces, only through its division into the opposing interests of those who command and those who produce. [Theodor W. Adorno, Hegel: Three Studies, translated by Shierry Weber Nicholsen (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1993), 79].

11 thoughts on “Adam Smith, revolutionary

  1. In a way, rather simply, it is only to say that real science, the sort that is humble in the gaze of evidence and is built up from the pieces of truth as they are found, is a revolutionary practice.
    The folly of contemporary academic Marxism of the Harvey variety is that is seeking to find a revolutionary analysis without direct relation to revolutionary practice and one which creates the truth as a function of the formula.
    This is in contrast to scientific socialism the purpose of which is to place the discovery of science at the service of the class.

    • You think that after all this bickering about whether this or that past philosopher was on the right side or not, there will be some energy left to incorporate the empirical?

      But honestly, I’ve never had much interest in Smith and can’t see why people bother so much with him. He’s pretty pedestrian, is he not?

      • I suppose, but only in the way that one might find Newton, Galileo, or Copernicus pedestrian in relationship to quantum mechanics, or Darwin so in relation to molecular biology.
        In hindsight the obvious seems simple. Yet, when we come to grasp that the earth is neither flat nor at the center of the universe and that gravitational pull and the arch of a projectile can be specifically and dependably calculated, the impact on humanity is profound.
        In the transition from the philosophical and intuitive comprehension of the social impact of economic law to the material comprehension Smith is a transitional figure who has not quite fully pinned the nail on the force of gravity. But he is THE transitional figure perhaps along with Mill Malthus and Ricardo.
        I am less concerned than is the writer above with Smith’s particular moral sentiments or his feelings toward Voltaire.
        What is more important to me is to avoid the cloistering, value coding, and intellectual sentimentalism that characterizes “Marxist” economics and separates it from the general science.
        If practitioners of scientific socialism are afraid to approach Smith or Keynes, or Mises and Friedman for that matter, directly on their own terms, then the are closer to “creation scientists” than they are to the attitudes of revolutionaries.

    • The question seems to me whether or not Marxism is still able to adequately grasp the unfolding of contemporary reality. What I mean is this: for Marx, the organized struggle of the working class against capital was one of the primary forces driving the development of capitalist society (and possibly pointing beyond capitalist society toward socialism). In the absence of such a self-conscious movement serving as the motor of History, with all the metaphysical baggage that word carries with it, society almost seems to be left spinning its wheels. Development increasingly appears to be simply the result of the automatic operations of capital on itself, an empty and unopposed automatism.

      I say this as someone who refuses to accept that this bleak situation is a permanent one.

      • You bring up a lot. I have been trying, not always successfully, to forgo the use of the term “Marxism” in favor of “scientific socialism” and to qualify this by identifying the project as I see it to be the advancement of the social interests of the working class. The SWP uses the term “communism, with a small ‘c,’”to get at the same idea.

        I feel no more qualified than anyone else to decide who is and who is not a Marxist, but much of what takes place today under the rubric of ‘Marxism’ is an attempt to resolve the contradictions of society within a theoretical realm. It is thus a highly formalized materialist philosophy conducted entirely within the realm of the ideal.

        I have pointed to my view in a couple of comments in your blog that I do not feel any sense that the movement of the class struggle has been stagnant.
        The history of the twentieth century as I see it was explosive from start to finish. Within a decade of the opening of the 21st century the fireworks keep going off. I take a very long view of history and think that this long view is actually, if one considers the movement of time from an evolutionary point of view, a short one.

        I was reading something yesterday about the domestication of dogs some 30,000, years ago by tribal cave dwellers in the European continent.

        Speaking in terms of current history I believe that the forces set in motion by the so called “Arab Spring” are only in their initial developmental stages. The Tahrir square movement was a sort of 1905 if you will allow me to stretch the analogy with Russian history. The current rise of the Kurdish national movement and the inevitability of a deeper involvement of U.S. and European imperialism in Libya and Syria may be understood borrowing the same analogy as reminiscent of the Russo-Japanese war.

        The basic operation of the business cycle promises not relief from the “great recession” but rather after nearly three years of meager recovery another dip, probably in the coming year.

        By all counts socialist organizations are seeing much greater receptivity to their views than at any time perhaps in the past half century. The working class is more sophisticated and cosmopolitan than it has ever been and a thousand times larger and more culturally aware than it was in 1848, and progressively so through 1875, 1905, 1917, 1949, 1959, 1968, 1979 1990 or even 2010. Historically the organization of the working class has not been a long progressive constant as Bernstein and contemporary Social Democrats and post Stalinist collaborationists would have it. Not the slow building of official unionism by methods acceptable to its professional and paid agents, but rather lightning fast as in the Auto strikes of the 1930s or the Teamsters strikes written about by Farrel Dobbs. The same was the case in the Russian revolution. The mass organization of the working class is historically a temporary phenomenon employed during times of heightened class struggle. As the class struggle recedes, either following victory or defeat, workers have limited interest in the sort of business unionism that marks the social democratic ideal of equitable class harmony.

        Part of what is wonderful about the autobiography of Preobrazhensky that I have been posting is the un-self-conscious commitment that he and his comrades had about directly propagandizing the working class.

        “I dreamed of a printing press” he writes. He felt no shame that his father had been a priest or that he was given a good education in high school. His intelligence and power as a writer was a weapon in his hand. He took it to the workers and by the age of 19 he was in the middle of the Presnya uprising of 1905. Upon their defeat he was back to work as a propagandist in the Urals within a week. He stayed at the task for what must have seemed a lifetime from 1905 until 1917. And then victory and then more struggle and then again defeat. So it is.

        The idea that there was a time, for which we must be nostalgic, when all the workers were ‘class conscious’ is rooted in fable, but the battles of resistance which have formed the social history of capitalism are real.

        Jump in if that is what you desire to do.

        ps, If I have not said this already, this blog, which provides a non-partisan, and even toned, not to mention beautifully decorated, venue for discussion is a contribution.

  2. Pingback: Adam Smith, revolutionary | Research Material

  3. Pingback: Adam Smith, revolutionary | Tierra y Libertad

  4. Pingback: Adam Smith, revolutionary | Research Material

  5. Pingback: Walking between precipices: An interview with Ernesto Laclau | The Charnel-House

  6. Pingback: The golden age of bourgeois portraiture, before the rise of photography | The Charnel-House

Leave a Reply